In the memoirs of his field work in
Brazil, Claude Lévi-Strauss describes
the moment when alternative realities became a thing of the past.1 At the end of his travels in the Amazon basin, and after working among native
peoples already in contact with the outside world, he got word of an “unknown”
tribe living “still savage” in the upland jungles:
There is no more thrilling prospect for the anthropologist than that of being the first white man to visit a particular native community. ... I was about to relive the experience of the early travellers and, through it, that crucial moment in modern thought when, thanks to the great voyages of discovery, a human community which believed itself to be complete and in its final form, suddenly learned, as if through the effect of a counter-revelation, that it was not alone, that it was part of a greater whole, and that, in order to achieve self-knowledge, it must first of all contemplate its unrecognizable image in this mirror, of which a fragment, forgotten by the centuries, was now about to cast, for me alone, its first and last reflection.2
There is no more thrilling prospect for the anthropologist than that of being the first white man to visit a particular native community. ... I was about to relive the experience of the early travellers and, through it, that crucial moment in modern thought when, thanks to the great voyages of discovery, a human community which believed itself to be complete and in its final form, suddenly learned, as if through the effect of a counter-revelation, that it was not alone, that it was part of a greater whole, and that, in order to achieve self-knowledge, it must first of all contemplate its unrecognizable image in this mirror, of which a fragment, forgotten by the centuries, was now about to cast, for me alone, its first and last reflection.2
The viewer is
bound to the object in mutual destruction, and, as at an apocalypse, the first
shall be last and the last shall be first. Lévi-Strauss, the last white man to thrill to a first encounter,
will thereby exhaust the world of possible other worlds. And the last unknown
tribe will lose its innocence of other worlds even as it resurrects, in the
“counter'revelation” it offers, the white man’s own lost belief in a world that
is final and complete.
By a coincidence of
opposites, this “unknown” was also the historical remnant of modem Europe’s
original Other. The tribe Lévi-Strauss
sought consisted of “the last descendants of the great Tupi communities
. .. whom the sixteentlvcentury travelers saw in their period of splendor.” In
this déjà-vu of a people
without history, Lévi- Strauss observes
the cause of Europe’s modernizing pluralism and the founding instance of his
science of man:
It was the accounts given by
these travellers which began the anthropological awareness of modern times; it
was their unintentional influence which set the political and moral philosophy
of the Renaissance on the road that was to lead to the French Revolution. To be
the first white man to set foot in a still-intact Tupi village would be to
bridge a gap of four hundred years and to find oneself on par with . . .
Montaigne who, in the chapter on cannibals in his Essays,
reflected on a conversation he had had with Tupi Indians whom he met at Rouen.3
For Lévi-Strauss, the prospect of a
belated return to his own historical origins is as thrilling as the promise of
a first encounter with the last unknown. Indeed it is quite unclear whether his
thrill derives from his anticipated encounter with savages or from his
historical transport, through them, back to the originary moment of his own
culture.
Lévi-Strauss arrives at the village
of people who refer to themselves as Mundé, and sets about studying their “way of thinking and social
organization.” But since he cannot speak their language and has no
interpreter, he must leave empty-handed, concluding: “After an enchanting trip
up-river, I had certainly found my savages. Alas! they were only too savage.”4
This sigh, heaved also in the title Tristes Tropiques, seems at first merely to express the
disappointment of not having been adequately equipped, of having made contact
without the tools to make sense. Yet it also describes the condition of mutual
indecipherability that the ethnographer anticipates and desires.
Lévi-Strauss retreats, the better
to prepare himself for surprise. Yet on his way back into the forest, embarked
on a search for yet another “still-savage” tribe, he encounters something truly
unexpected. Rounding a bend, he finds himself facing two natives traveling in
the opposite direction. They are the leaders of the very tribe that the
anthropologist seeks. Having “resolved to leave their village for good and join
the civilized world,”5 they bear with them their most precious
possession, a live harpy eagle, as a gift for their future hosts.
The
anthropologist arrives too early or too late. Either he encounters innocence
and, “alas,” cannot penetrate it, or he finds it already on its way to him and
therefore no longer pure. Lévi-Strauss
bribes the leaders to go back to their village and the eagle, their totem, is
“unceremoniously dumped by the side of a stream, where it seemed doomed to
die.” Even while noting that the jettisoned bird meant the demise of the
tribe’s identity, Lévi-Strauss returns
the natives to their home, where they will play-act as savage informants, as
inhabitants of a reality alternative to ours because ignorant of alternatives,
forgetting for the while that they had already sought, and thus dwelt within,
our now fully ubiquitous world.
For
Lévi-Strauss, the forest is
not paradisal but tragic. The savage other cannot be observed because it is
“alas! too savage,” or it will have already discovered us and, measured against
modernity, it again is “alas! poor savage.” Lévi-Strauss’s sadness may be merely a last Romantic yearning for
lost innocence combined with the admonishment “we murder to dissect.” Yet it
has relevance to our present situation at the end of the millennium, in an era
of economic globalization, as we turn to wonders not in forests at the world’s
edge, but in unrecognized historical cultures of a premodem past.
The
anthropologist’s failed encounter with the unknown locates “alternative realities”
in history, defining them as both the founding modern experience and a retrospective
fantasy to an earlier time. Even as he laments the passing of indigenous
cultures, Lévi-Strauss celebrates
his inheritance from the first European explorers, taking as much pleasure in
his kinship with Montaigne as in his difference from the savages. More
important, he argues that, in its encounter with the New World, the Old World
became conscious of its contingency, as a possible but not necessary world, and
further that this contingency of worlds gave anthropology its object.
Traditionally
defined as that which is but could be otherwise (or, in modal logic, as that
which is both not necessary and not impossible), “contingency” is at once
settling and unsettling.6 Europe’s unexpected encounter with America
made surprises more expectable. Yet it also occasioned a yearning for lost
certainty that, in time, fueled the very impulse to explore. Something of this
benign, reflective exoticism is present in Lévi-Strauss’s encounter with the too-savage savages. Unlike the second
tribe that he eventually studies, but that he must drive back to its village in
order to do so, the supposedly still-indigenous Mundé are what he really wants to discover,
even though their indecipherability leaves him “with a feeling of emptiness.” For
according to a central Western myth, savages are defined as such by their
hermeticism, by their possessing not just a different view of the world, but
no proper “view” at all: a reality that so embraces them that it does not admit
of, or even give rise to the thought of, alternatives. The New World native,
still unaware that it is but one world that he inhabits, becomes indeed a
reflection of the European explorer, but of him before he discerns, in his
encounter with the native, his own contingency.
This
state of dwelling in a “world” without knowing it became a modern ideal. It was
summed up in an untranslatable aphorism by Ludwig Feuerbach, composed a few
years before the philosopher’s death in 1872: “In
der Unwissenheit ist der Mensch bei sich zu
Hause, in seiner Heimat; in der Wissenschaft in der Fremde”7
(meaning, roughly, “in unknowing man is at home with himself, in his native
place; in knowledge, he is in exile”). The sentence surprises by breaking the
connection between knowledge and certainty. Certainty, one thinks, depends on
knowing, and it is the task of science (Wissenschaft)
as defined by Rationalist thought since Descartes, to increase certitude,
illuminate obscurity, and thus to domesticate the world. In stating, instead,
that unknowing fosters belonging, Feuerbach, condensing the Romantic critique
of Enlightenment, argues not that science has failed to produce, but rather
that it has overproduced knowledge, and of a form that increases uncertainty.
Where, for Thales, the first scientist, the world was still “full of Gods”
(Plato, Laws 10.899B), for the postscientific
temperament, the world now is full of theories, of infinite, contingent
representations of world. Feuerbach yearns for what the late Hans Blumenberg
once termed “the enclaves of unknowing after the triumph of Enlightenment.”8
In late- nineteenth-century Germany, these enclaves were discovered in the
vanishing countryside close to home, or, more powerfully, in Ferdinand Tônnies’s ideal of the closed,
local, natural Gemeinschaft of the medieval
town as set against the open, global, and constructed urban Gesellschaft of the modem world.9
In
our own century, such imagined enclaves lie further afield, or are discerned,
as in Lévi-Strauss, at the
point of their extinction. Yet they survive in our thought in various
vestigial phantasms of spatial belonging, in which, against the contingency and
pluralism of the world, there is set the radically necessary and singular
placement of the body. It appears crucially in Edmund Husserl’s notion of Lebenswelt,10 which influenced Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s “science of
pre-science”: the utopia of an experience of world before science split “life”
and “world.” The idea also animates Pierre Bour- dieu’s term “habitus,”
defined, with reference to Poincaré,
as “a system of axes linked unalterably to our bodies and carried about
with us wherever we go.”11 In the writing of history today, it
appears most often in idealizing descriptions of premodem spatiality and
carnality, and in attempts at describing the medieval conception of the world
as the representative alternative historical reality.12
Alternative
realities, from this point of view, are those that do not know alternative
realities. Life-worlds left with their prejudices intact, they are antithetical
to our modem consciousness of contingency, which says that “truth is made
rather than found,”13 even as it is only through this consciousness
that one recognizes an alternative reality. For as Blumenberg argued early in
his career, to speak of realities in the plural makes sense neither in the
antique philosophical idea of the reality of instantaneous evidence, nor in
the medieval theological doctrine of reality as guaranteed by God. Within the
latter view, there may be diabolical deceptions of all kinds, but these are not
plural realities but the plurality of falsehood. Only when reality is conceived
as the result of the realization of specific contexts—in Blumenberg’s terms,
when it is regarded as a certainty that constitutes itself only successively,
as a never-final and absolute consistency,
or as a consistency that refers always to a future in which elements can
emerge that might explode the earlier consistency and reveal it to be
unreal—only then can one speak of “their” reality, or of “that” society’s
reality, as being simultaneously real and unique.14
Since
the late eighteenth century, the historicity of the idea that reality might be
plural is most intensely argued with reference to the Weltanschauung. Kant coined the word in 1790 to
explain why the “world,” as a totality, cannot be the object of a “view,”
except from a transcendent perspective that, when intimated, occasions feelings
of the sublime (Critique of Judgment).15
Once launched, the term took on an independent life. At one level, worldview
came to indicate the specificity with which each person, culture, or era
experiences the world. At another level, it described a subjective relation to
the world that was historically specific, and that emerged in Europe during the
modem period in the wake of secularization. In this second, narrower definition,
worldview implied a particular, self-consciousness that reality is known only
through the specific way it is seen. Under such pressures as science’s
disclosure of plural worlds, the New World’s evidence of unknown peoples, and
the early modem religious wars’ mutually exclusive truths, people—so the story
goes—became conscious that their world, its consistency, truth, and purpose,
was contingent on their having a specific viewpoint on it. Instead of
lamenting this as a loss, the philosophers of Weltanschauung,
from Christoph M. Wieland, Alexander von Humboldt, and Wilhelm Dilthey to
Husserl, Karl Mannheim, and Karl Jaspers, celebrated viewpoint-awareness as a
new center of spiritual meaning and as an antidote against the ever-expanding,
decentered world being discovered by science. Worldview, in its constitutive
acceptance of alternative realities, thus contrasted both to the lost
wholeness of the medieval Christian conception of world and to science’s
dehumanized universe. Its appearance within European thought was believed to
mark the hiatus of the modern era by distinguishing the eras “Middle Ages” and
“Renaissance.”
Because
it paired world specifically with “view,” because, that is, it articulated the
intertwining of object and subject with reference to the faculty of sight, the
term Weltanschauung had an illustrious career
in art history. While normative aesthetics took art’s task to be the imitation
of reality, and therefore judged individual works against that single standard,
the historical study of art, emerging as an academic subject in the nineteenth
century, was founded on the belief that different cultures represent reality
differently, and that apparently “unrealistic” styles are not to be judged as
wrong but to be interpreted as realizations of different contexts. The
elaboration of a value-neutral history of style, together with contemporary
critical preferences for stylistic uniqueness as the mark of genius, drew
attention to the fact that the world, when visualized in art, was contingent on
the particularities of person, place, and time. Weltanschauung,
therefore, was both a consequence of art-historical consciousness and a
felicitous motto for the discipline. It announces that art as evidence of the
way persons and peoples saw the world ought to be foundational to the
understanding of history: pictures are worldviews.
Perhaps
the most pivotal use of the term is Erwin Panofsky’s in his 1927 essay “Perspective
as Symbolic Form.” Perspective, equated here with Weltanschauung,
is both historical and ahistorical. On the one hand, contesting the view that
linear perspective as developed in Renaissance art is a categorically truer
way of presenting the world, Panofsky asks of his historical material “not
whether it has perspective, but which perspective it has.”16 Every
artwork has its own perspective corresponding to the particular worldview of
the larger culture. On the other hand, linear perspective, in its method of
making world contingent on viewpoint, corresponds to the modem Weltanschauung in the more narrow sense, as a
historically specific consciousness of positionality—what Nietzsche famously
termed “perspectivism.”
Jan
van Eyck’s Madonna of Chancellor Rolin of
around 1435 is amenable to these terms (Figure 1). In its construction of deep
space, conveyed by the receding lines of the tiled floor and by the river
landscape stretching to the horizon, it locates a sacred scene—the apparition
of the Virgin—in a world as if coextensive with our own. Indeed the movement
into the picture exerts such a force, and yields so many delights, that the
exchange displayed across the picture, between Rolin and the Virgin and Christ,
seems eclipsed. The artist employs landscape to mark that exchange: a distant
bridge carries Christ’s gesture of blessing over to Rolin’s praying hands. What
Jacob Burckhardt termed the Renaissance discovery of the individual and the
world finds its emblem here. The necessary and constitutive connection between
viewer and viewed opens a chasm between “medieval man” and his faith. And a
newly rehabilitated curiosity about this world,17 embodied,
visually, in the turned figure in the middle ground shown beholding the
landscape, replaces ascetic thought directed to an afterlife. Secularization,
the process of an increasing worldliness, thus seems the historical condition
of the worldview; and the artist Jan van Eyck, probably portrayed as the red-
turbaned man standing beside the surrogate viewer, offers his created reality
as alternative to God’s.
Historians
today distrust such apparent modernity. They push van Eyck’s picture back into
a remoter age, arguing that its mundane world is brimming with symbols, like
the Master of Flemalle’s famous background fire-screen, which functions
visually as the Virgin’s halo.18 They claim that, in the medieval
worldview, reality was constituted by signs pointing beyond themselves to God.19
And they maintain that the hiddenness of these signs in van Eyck indicates not
his secular vision but the invisibility of faith to our secular worldview. How
then are we modems expected to see that invisible border between us and the
past? Are there pictures of the threshold to an alternative historical
reality?
Daniel
Boorstin’s best-selling history, The Discoverers,
reproduces a line drawing on its cover, described as an “early 16th century
woodcut.”20 In this image, a kneeling
Figure 1. Jan van Eyck, Madonna of Chancellor Nicolas Rolin, ca. 1435. Louvre, Paris.
Figure 1. Jan van Eyck, Madonna of Chancellor Nicolas Rolin, ca. 1435. Louvre, Paris.
pilgrim gingerly pokes his head, hand, and walking staff through a scrim of stars, to peer from one reality into a host of others. He leaves behind a local Lebenswelt of churches, forests, and fields, where the stars are fixed to their spheres, and sun and moon, outfitted with faces, betray an anthropomorphic, pre-Copernican cosmology. The wanderer’s head has just breached the boundary of this reality, enabling him to wonder at an infinite succession of worlds arranged as circles placed crosswise to the outline of his sphere. One heavenly body looks mechanical, as if made by Descartes’s watchmaker God. What better way to illustrate the historical passage of man, the discoverer, from the closed world of the Middle Ages to the open universe of modernity! While drawn in a quaint medieval style, the woodcut seems to foresee the future.
Yet
this quaintness spells trouble. Certain areas of foliage look more William
Morris than Dürer; certain hybrids, hard to imagine as sixteenth-century, like
the machine- tooled cosmos beside the Mother Goose moon: these indicate a
medievalizing print. Indeed, it is an illustration from a popular book on
meteorology by Camille Flammar- ion, published in Paris in 1888.21
Boorstin’s publishers cropped and colored it but forgot to check the source.
One might lament the demise of so perfect a picture of breached worldviews. If
Boorstin’s cover shows the picture one might want, its error raises the
question: Can such a picture exist?
Martin Heidegger
gave one answer in a lecture delivered in 1938 and published under the title
“Die Zeit des Weltbildes.”22 According to Heidegger, the symptoms of
the modern age are the hegemony of science, the aesthetization of art as object
of experience, the definition of human activity as “culture,” and the
desacralization of the world. And all these are reduced to the process by which
the modem subject constitutes itself as subject by becoming the viewer of a
world laid out before it as in a picture. The world picture, in Heidegger’s
terms, is not a picture of the world but the world as picture. And the “time of
the world picture” is the modern era. The argument reiterates the philosophy of
Weltanschauung, even as its ideological tenor
has become more crudely antimodernist. Heidegger laments both the loss of human
grounding through perspectivism’s abstraction and the functionalization of the
world through technology. Nonetheless, his argument is useful, for it states in
categorical terms that there can be no transition from medieval to modern world
pictures. For according to Heidegger, people in the Middle Ages did not
understand the world as a picture, because for them the world, as created by
God, places the individual not before it, as its viewer, and therefore as
possessor of Weltanschauung, but only somewhere
within it, as a mere created thing that will be viewed and judged only by an
omnivoyant, omnipresent God. I shall attempt to take up Heidegger’s challenge
by considering some images from around 1500 in which medieval and modern world
pictures seem to overlap as in a half-legible palimpsest.
Jheronimus
Anthoniszoon van Aken (d. 1516), who signed his works “Hieronymus Bosch,” is an
art-historical monster. Called in his century “the inventor of devils,” the
painter of freaks, chimeras, and things, in Lodovico Guicciardini’s 1567
account, “fan- tastiques, & bizares,”23 Bosch is himself the
great unknown of the Northern tradition, the artist who did not, and still does
not, seem to fit. Unforeseeable from what came before him, he remains largely
un-understood. He is the still-savage major master of the European tradition.
His first public defender, the Spaniard Don Felipe de Guevara, reports in 1560
that the people saw Bosch’s pictures “as a monstrosity, as something outside
the rules of what is taken to be natural.”24 The impossible, in
Greek adynaton, is contingency’s outer limit,
and it was there that Bosch was felt to press. Guevara, writing for a courtly
audience around 1560, admitted that the artist “painted strange things, but
only because he set his theme in Hell, for which, as he wanted to represent
devils, he devised compositions of unusual things.” While hoffähig as portraitist of demons, Bosch occasioned
monstrous interpretations. His most famous masterpiece, the triptych sometimes
called the Garden of Earthly Delights, has
been taken to represent, variously, the world before the Flood, life in Eden,
the apotheosis of sin, a utopia of a never-fallen humanity, a satanic comedy, a
satire on vanity by a Northern Savonarola, a bourgeois parody of courtly love,
and a sermon on fantasy. One historian, Wilhelm Fraenger, took Bosch’s alterity
at face value and read the Garden as an
actual altarpiece to a non-Christian god.25 Erwin Panofsky, playing
it safe, broke off his monumental account of early Netherlandish painting
before discussing Bosch with the learned disclaimer, “This, too high for my
wit, / I prefer to omit”26—a version, to be sure, of Lévi-Strauss’s “Alas! too savage!”
Indeed
beyond matters of local interpretation, there is a savagery in Bosch that
affects us still today, as the assembled subaltern others of medieval
society—the beggars, thieves, witches, and heretics; the quacks and magicians;
the Jews, Moslems, and blacks—are all gathered as in some curiosity cabinet of
cruelty, there to be vilified, tortured, and damned. In Bosch, Christian
culture reveals its barbarism by self- righteously punishing all realities
alternative to its own. Collector of stigmatized others, Bosch is himself the
quintessential alternative reality, medieval narrow-mindedness on the rampage
against competing worldviews. And indeed as soon as one goes to interpret him,
his alterity challenges and seduces. To some scholars his art seems encrypted,
and demands a specific key, which is often sought in codes he condemns, such as
those of alchemy.27 To others, he pictures the historical loss of
any such key.28 Against the medieval Christian symbolic code, it is
argued, Bosch stages the movement to modem semantic uncertainty, in which what
something is stands in an unstable, contingent relation to what it means. I
shall try to circumvent questions of meaning by concentrating on issues of
place and placement. I shall first locate and describe Bosch’s pictures of
world. Then I shall attempt to place his pictures in the world. Understood as
world pictures, Bosch’s paintings will help situate the history of knowledge
(Feuerbach’s Wissenschaft) within a history
of the emergence of that strange object, art.
The
Spanish cleric and erudite Fray Joseph de Siguen^a, in his prose masterpiece The History of the Order of St. Jerome (1605),
defended Bosch against those who term his paintings “non-sense” (disparates) and “call him unjustly a heretic.”29
Disparates is a hard word to gloss. Derived
from the Latin disparare (“to
separate”) and related to the English “disparate,” it came to denote, within
Spanish art theory of the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, all that is
physically monstrous and deformed, intellectually absurd, aesthetically
incongruous, or morally objectionable. Originally a term of disparagement, it
soon became a descriptive category naming a specific, popular mode of art,
literature, and drama that aimed at grotesque and playfully arbitrary forms: in
poetry, for example, nonsense verse; in theater, the farce-intermezzo (entremés)-, and in painting, drolleries or
capriccios in the Boschian manner.30 For such writers as Lope de
Vega, Manuel de Melo, and Francesco Quevado, Bosch’s pictures defined what disparates
meant. This makes it difficult, in turn, to understand Bosch through this term,
except by noting that, applied to his art, it can both describe and disparage,
naming either what Bosch’s pictures depict, or what they themselves are. A
Spanish satirist in 1600 could vilify his competitors by comparing their farces
(or persons) to the disparates of Bosch,
thereby deliberately confusing satire with satirist.
The
ambivalence of “non-sense”—whether it describes Bosch’s art or what it
depicts—applies also to the more serious accusation dismissed by Siguen^a, that
the artist was a heretic. We encounter the notion again in a venomous tract
from 1635 attacking Bosch’s most famous literary heir, Quevado. In the Tribunal de la justa venganza, Quevado
appears in league with Bosch, the “ataista.”31 It is possible that
seventeenth- century observers in Spain, like some historians in our time,
regarded Bosch’s various images of apostasy as themselves apostate images;
their view might also have been strengthened during the Thirty Years’ War, when
Bosch’s native Low Countries were aligned, as Protestant, against Catholic
Spain.32 Yet the charge of unbelief was at least as slippery in 1635
as it is today for Fraenger’s revisionist account. Quevado himself had broached
the question in his El alguacil endemoniado (1607). Bosch appears as a visitor to hell, who, when asked why he
paints his demons so absurdly, answers: “Because I never believed the devils
were real.” Scholars of Bosch remain uncertain about the artist’s faith:
whether his monsters are devils or nonsense, and whether, therefore, his disparates travesty false religion or reveal
religion itself to be a travesty.
Siguena’s
answer is religiously orthodox and seriously intended. Even his strangest
pictures—which Siguenga calls “macaronic,” meaning a jumbling of high and low—
express the verdict of the prophets on the vanity of the world: “The idea and
the art of this manner are based on Isaiah 40:6, where the messenger of God
says, ‘All flesh is grass.’ ” Siguenfa understands Bosch within the original
Christian idea of contingency. Borrowing from Latinized Aristotelian logic,
Christian theologians of the Middle Ages coined the term contingentia to express the ontological
constitution of the world as that which was created out of nothing, is
sustained only through divine Will, and shall pass away. The world, by this
definition, is not necessary; it could just as well not have been, or been
otherwise, and it owes its existence to God’s unconditional being.3’
As I shall suggest, Bosch pictures world in its constitution as that which
could be otherwise, and so in order to teach his viewer a proper contempt for
this world.
The
so-called Hay Wain perfectly expresses
Bosch’s world view (Figure 2). Dating to
about 1500,
this signed triptych was described by sixteenth-century sources, and exists
today in two copies, both of them inferior and in poor condition, in the Prado
and the Escorial. Already
Siguena names the hay at the picture’s center as the “grass” referred to in
Isaiah. All surrounding matter, from the vagabond on the triptych’s outer wings
to the interior’s spectacles of Paradise, earth, and hell, would thus embellish
the central figure of the vanity of the world. World appears here in multiple,
overlapping models—what Michel de Certeau, with reference to Bosch, termed
“spatial polyglo- tism.”34 It is present as the subject matter, the
hay, which is both a biblical and a vernacular proverbial emblem of world as
contingent. Hay fills the pouches of the folk depicted, or sticks to their
fingers as their attachment to the world. Bundled on the wagon, it looks like a
misshapen globe, or better, like the terrestrial lower half of the spherical
“world,” such as we see on the outer shutters of Bosch’s Garden of Earthly Delights
(Figure 3). Set against a landscape, the lovers on top of the hay would thus sit on what would be, according to this geographical model, the inhabitable surface of the earth. The hay thereby becomes an allegorical world within the world. Several early compositions after the Hay Wain make this valency more apparent. In tapestries in the Royal Palace in Madrid and in the Escorial, the whole scene of the original triptych’s central panel is reproduced within a circle that, fitted at the upper right with a cross
Figure 3. Hieronymus Bosch, , closed state, ca. 1510, panel painting. Prado, Madrid.
(Figure 3). Set against a landscape, the lovers on top of the hay would thus sit on what would be, according to this geographical model, the inhabitable surface of the earth. The hay thereby becomes an allegorical world within the world. Several early compositions after the Hay Wain make this valency more apparent. In tapestries in the Royal Palace in Madrid and in the Escorial, the whole scene of the original triptych’s central panel is reproduced within a circle that, fitted at the upper right with a cross
Figure 3. Hieronymus Bosch, , closed state, ca. 1510, panel painting. Prado, Madrid.
and surrounded at the base by sea monsters and waves, reads like a giant orb or Reich- sapfel
floating on the deep.35 Bosch elsewhere superimposes the outlines of
the world’s orb over an ordinary scene, as in the panel sometimes called the
Stone Operation,36 In this panel, now in the
Prado, the round format of the image itself, together with the curving border
between middle and background that, located halfway up the roundel,
could double as
the equator of a transparent globe, extend the picture’s message of folly to
the world as a “whole,” represented both as mundane landscape and as outlined
globe. The picture thus becomes a macaronic world map.
In
the Hay Wain, world is most of all present as
the triptych’s depiction of landscape. Bosch constructs the first genuine Weltlandschafth in Western painting. The
bird’s-eye view unfolds sideways to Paradise and hell, and outward into space,
toward infinity at the horizon. Narrow at the sides but expansive to the
distance, Bosch imagines a world limited in time but infinite in space.
Placing the picture’s spectator simultaneously as a pawn in salvation history
and as the privileged viewer of an endless universe, Bosch’s world picture is
both medieval and modern, closed and open, allegory and map.
Bosch
offers us a beautiful world view only to anathematize that world as sin. The
principle vice is avarice, defined as any positive relation to the world. All
other sins— gluttony, anger, lust, etc.—crowd round as versions of love of the
world.58 Bosch depicts sin both by showing sinners and by telling
sin’s story: fall of the rebel angels and man, exile from Paradise, profusion
of sin, and final punishment. World history processes as a false triumph from
bad to worse. Bosch shows ephemerality by endowing it with a rigid, necessary
structure. Sin might appear chaotic, as bodies grasping helter- skelter at the
hay, yet the hay is resolutely at the picture’s center. It founds a symmetry
that endows the whole with the character of a cosmic diagram. Hell is the
negative of Paradise, its black towers being a ruined version of Paradise’s
curious rocks. And these antitheses surround a composition whose center is
maintained both by the hay wagon and by Christ, who, displaying his wounds,
appears above a rainbow in the clouds.
Of
course, Christ, the hay, and the viewer are only presently aligned. Bosch
reminds us of the imminence of this skewing, this future structural
dissolution, by suggesting the instantaneous “after” in details like the woman
futilely erecting a ladder on the moving mass of hay, and the turbaned man with
his already-toppled ladder about to be crushed by the wagon’s wheels. In that
very next moment, when the hay passes to the right, drawing with it the
viewer’s gaze, Christ will remain behind at the center now abandoned by the
world. True, one might imagine that Christ, peering down from heaven, will keep
pace with our movements, as do the sun and moon as we walk the earth, or that
the cloud through which Christ peers will cling to the hay, as the perpetual
promise of salvation. Such trust in permanence, however, is at odds with the
picture’s overall message of vanity. It represents that forgetfulness of time,
death, and punishment that all actors exemplify and that stands condensed in
the motif of the lovers in the verweile-doch
of lust.
The
picture’s center is but a momentary alignment of Christ, the world, and the
viewer. From any other vantage point in time and space, this relation will be
skewed, indeed as it is for all the depicted figures in their rage for the
world as center. While the panel’s rigid alignment gives the whole the
appearance of a necessary structure, it announces that this structure is
contingent on the beholding subject. The picture asks the viewer to render a
decision on the world here and now. And within the picture’s logic, the here
and now is the hay itself. It is that shapeless, blank, and mobile mass—
equivalent to world—that constitutes the picture’s center and principle object,
and that appears venerated like a god.
The
reference to idolatry—as a general fetishism of things—raises questions about
the form and function of Bosch’s triptych. We do not know the Hay Wain’s original context, whether it was
intended as an altarpiece for a Christian altar or an artwork for a secular
collection. We know it stood in the church of the royal palace and monastery at
El Escorial in the eighteenth century, but it arrived there via secular art
collections. Yet whether for a church or Kunstkammer,
the Hay Wain’s triptych format, its symmetrical
composition, and even its temporal framework, which places “before” to the left
and “after” to the right, derives from altarpieces. More specifically, the
scheme whereby side panels representing Paradise and hell flank a central scene
of impending damnation recalls the format of Last Judgment altarpieces, which
Bosch himself fashioned in numerous versions, including one very large
ensemble commissioned by Philip the Fair in 1504 and now lost, but believed to
be close to an extant triptych in the Academy of Fine Arts in Vienna.’9
The
retable altarpiece is the model for the Hay Wain’s
geometry and for its assurance that contingency is framed in a necessary
order. In church space this order would extend out from the altarpiece to the
altar before it, and beyond that, to a world thought to be oriented around
church and altar. For an altar is a sacred place, elevated above ordinary
locations not only through the sacrament performed on it, but also through
special rites of consecration, which entombed in the altar certain sacred
things: martyr’s relics, consecrated eucharistic hosts, incense kernels burned
during the episcopal rite of the altar’s consecration, and documents
guaranteeing the authenticity of all these.40 Endowed with praesentia, the altar oriented space around itself
as around an absolute center. It directed gazes eastward toward Jerusalem as
well as, invariably, toward the miracle performed at it, when the elements of
bread and wine were, in Aquinas’s term, “transubstantiated” into Christ’s real
flesh and blood through the agency of the priest. In the late Middle Ages, this
miracle became, for the laity, above all a visual spectacle, in which the
consecrated host was elevated and placed in special framing tabernacles for
prolonged ostentation. The laity received the host in an ocular communion, a manducatio per visum, almost as efficacious as
gustation proper.41 Image ensembles erected behind the altar table
reiterated in their centralized plan the structured attention of salvific seeing.
They functioned variously to glorify, explain, or even bring intercession to
the greater spectacle enacted before them, a spectacle that kept all eyes fixed
on Christ present, again in scholastic terms, as the substance of the accident
of the bread. Bosch himself visualized this mystery in a scene of the Mass of
St. Gregory that
adorns the outer panels of his Epiphany
altarpiece, now in the Prado in Madrid.42 In the Hay Wain, in a gesture that has neither precedent
or sequel, the center of this absolute geography is occupied by hay, by the
emblem, indeed, of accident without substance.
Bosch’s
Hay Wain probably did not originally stand
behind an altar. Perhaps it served as a devotional aid in a place of private
worship, such as a privatorium. More likely, however, it was, from the start, a
precious work of art within a princely or patrician collection. There it might
have functioned to admonish against the enchantment of earthly treasures like
itself. The curiosity served by the Renaissance Kunst'
und Wunderkammer would be repositioned within the medieval catalogue of
the vices. A secular context, moreover, would explain the hay’s valence as
idol. Replacing the cult object at the center of the Christian retable with an
image of contingency, the Hay Wain would make
a moral point about its very status as a worldly thing, and even about the
historical passage from sacred to profane that it, as a hybrid art altarpiece,
negotiated. Bosch carries over into the new, secular space of art the absolute
geography of the sacred, even if only as a ghostly frame. In this space,
beginning and end, good and evil, truth and falsehood have fixed and necessary
places, structured locations that, in Bosch, are consubstantial with the
painted panel itself in its material geometry.
Bosch’s
portrait of the world’s sphere fits snugly in place on the outer panels of the Garden of Earthly Delights (Figure 3). The earth’s
geography conforms perfectly to the picture’s geometry because earth was made
by God, who appears in the upper left in the position of a divine geometer. The
Psalmist’s words inscribed at the panels’ tops reminds us of this ontological
dependency, this relation between a necessary agent and a created, and thus
contingent, thing: “For He spoke, and it was; He commanded, and it stood.” This
providential geography recalls medieval world maps. In the Ebstorf mappamundi, dating from around 1235 and destroyed
in 1943, geographic and geometric centers—the navel of the world and of the
midpoint of the map—converge on Jerusalem and on Christ, shown resurrected
from his grave.43 Beginning in the fourth century and culminating in
the crusaders’ rallying cry “ad sepulchrum
Domini," Jesus’ empty tomb constituted the place of places around
which the world organized itself as around an absolute center. In the Ebstorf
example, the world is circumscribed by Christ’s body: his head appears in the
far east, at Paradise, while his feet and hands mark the points west, north,
and south.
According
to Horst Appuhn, the map originally served as an Easter Tapestry for the ground
before the altar of the nun’s choir of the Ebstorf cloister.44 This
further “orients” things, for the map itself would face east, with the altar.
The Hereford Map of around 1290 similarly
inscribes contingent space into the necessary space of God.45
According to an eighteenth-century source, the map once stood at the central of
a triptych backing the Hereford cathedral’s high altar. Flanked by shutters
depicting (at the left) the annunciating angel Gabriel and (to the right) the
Virgin, the map situated God’s historical and liturgical entrance in the
world, as Christ’s incarnation through Mary and as his presence in altar’s
rite. Read as a version of a mappamundi, Bosch’s
Garden superimposes on absolute geography a
different space. The landscape of the newly created earth, shown as a disk
floating on the waters of the deep, recedes into depth as if observed by a
human eye in positional space.46 Bosch brings together in a single
picture two distinct models of world: one contingent on God, the other
contingent on viewpoint.
It would be the
contingency of perspective that, henceforth, defines the image for European
painting until this century. In it became apparent what Immanuel Kant was to
state near the opening of the Critique of Pure
Reason: “It is, therefore, solely from a human standpoint that we can
speak of space.” Pieter Bruegel the Elder’s world- scapes, made in dialogue
with Bosch’s, already bear eloquent witness to this troubled process. In the
Vienna Carrying of the Cross, dated 1564, the
single, framed, rectangular panel, made to be experienced aesthetically in the
Kunstkammer, has severed its ties to church
space
(Figure 4). Bruegel positions the viewer before a vast prospect of the mundane world, and he dramatizes this vertiginous expansion by means of people rushing toward Golgotha in the distance. Christ, the picture’s subject, is overlooked by all except the holy figures mourning in the foreground. Bruegel personifies humanity’s indifference toward Christ in the figure of Simon of Cyrene at the lower left. According to the Gospel, soldiers compelled the Cyrenian to bear Christ’s cross (Matt. 27:32; Mark 15:21); in Bruegel, Simon appears held back by his wife, who, wearing a rosary, stands for false, outer piety. While the multitude march forward with their backs to Christ, Simon, the one called to carry Christ’s burden, draws back in the viewer’s direction. Christ thus kneels between two immense indifferences, one near the picture’s vanishing point, in that empty circle of gawking people on the horizon, the other near the viewpoint, where the beholder’s faith is tested. Although tiny in the landscape, Christ appears at the exact center of the panel, and from there looks directly back at us. This vestige of absolute space, of an order located in places themselves (here the painted mark) rather than in positions from which they are observed, is a legacy of Bosch. It appears most momentously in one of Bosch’s surviving retable altarpieces.
(Figure 4). Bruegel positions the viewer before a vast prospect of the mundane world, and he dramatizes this vertiginous expansion by means of people rushing toward Golgotha in the distance. Christ, the picture’s subject, is overlooked by all except the holy figures mourning in the foreground. Bruegel personifies humanity’s indifference toward Christ in the figure of Simon of Cyrene at the lower left. According to the Gospel, soldiers compelled the Cyrenian to bear Christ’s cross (Matt. 27:32; Mark 15:21); in Bruegel, Simon appears held back by his wife, who, wearing a rosary, stands for false, outer piety. While the multitude march forward with their backs to Christ, Simon, the one called to carry Christ’s burden, draws back in the viewer’s direction. Christ thus kneels between two immense indifferences, one near the picture’s vanishing point, in that empty circle of gawking people on the horizon, the other near the viewpoint, where the beholder’s faith is tested. Although tiny in the landscape, Christ appears at the exact center of the panel, and from there looks directly back at us. This vestige of absolute space, of an order located in places themselves (here the painted mark) rather than in positions from which they are observed, is a legacy of Bosch. It appears most momentously in one of Bosch’s surviving retable altarpieces.
If measured by
its influence, the Temptation of St. Anthony,
now in Lisbon, and dated to around 1510-15, is Bosch’s most important work
(Figure 5). More than twenty copies of it exist, and it inspired a huge number
of imitations until well into the seventeenth century.47 Bosch
himself made several versions of the theme. Siguenfa, who was close to the
Spanish court that zealously collected Bosch, reports that “this painting is
seen often; one is in the chapter house of the Order of St. Jerome; another in
the cell of the prior; two in the gallery of the Infanta; some in my cell,
which I often read
Figure 4- Pieter Bruegel the Elder, Christ Carrying the Cross, 1564. Kunsthistorisches Museum, Vienna. Photograph courtesy Bildarchiv Foto Marburg.
Figure 4- Pieter Bruegel the Elder, Christ Carrying the Cross, 1564. Kunsthistorisches Museum, Vienna. Photograph courtesy Bildarchiv Foto Marburg.
and immerse
myself in.”481 would like to have seen Siguenfa’s cell, where
Bosch’s pic- tures proliferated like the demons they depict. The pious brother
seems to have used them for his religious devotions, although by his time the
vast majority of Boschian St. Anthony panels were in secular art collections.
Originally, though, the Lisbon panels almost certainly functioned as an
altarpiece. Contemporary documents inform us that in 1490 Bosch painted the
“outer wings” of a retable in the chapel of the Illustre Lieve- Vrouwe
Broederschap in the Cathedral of St. John in s’Hertogenbosch; and he seems also
to have executed altarpiece wings for the cathedral’s High Altar, as well as
for an altar dedicated to St. Michael.49 And we know that altars
dedicated to St. Anthony had currency during this period: the retable for the
hospital of the Order of St. Anthony in Isenheim, with its sculpted shrine from
around 1490 by Nikolas Hagenower and later wings by a painter called
Griinewald, is one famous example.
Yet
as an altarpiece, Bosch’s triptych is certainly unique. For one thing, winged
reta- bles ordinarily enclosed a cult image in their shrine, like Hagenower’s
enthroned St. Anthony, which claimed to make present the power of the saint
himself. Or the central image narrated a significant event: a moment in Heilsgeschichte or a martyr’s death. Bosch’s
triptych offers no proper cult image, and the specific stories from Anthony’s
life, as
told in such popular, late medieval hagiographies,50 are exiled to
the wings: Anthony’s return to his cave, his temptation by the beautiful queen,
etc. The central panel extracts the saint from the chain of necessary events
and represents him in general attitude of devotion. Bosch’s badly preserved Hermit Saints Triptych, now in the Doge’s Palace in
Venice, extends this strategy through all three panels.51 Saints
Anthony, Jerome, and Giles appear there not as objects of devotion but as
subjects in devotion. Neither cultic presences nor actors within significant
events, they offer, through their inward attitude, a model of subjective piety.
Siguemja,
always Bosch’s best reader, wrote that whereas most artists “paint man as he
looks from outside, this artist has the courage to paint him as he is
inwardly.”52 This focus on inwardness, congenial to the
Counter-Reformation spirituality of Siguenga and of the Royal Monastery of San
Lorenzo in El Escorial, was also in tune with lay piety in Bosch’s time,
influenced as it was by the devotio modema.1'
But what does Bosch’s inner man look like?
In
the Lisbon triptych, we must work to find this inner man, for he is all but
lost in the hellish spectacle all around. According to tradition, the
temptation of St. Anthony was this kind of spectacle.54 It was a
chaos of phantasms conjured by the devil to tempt and terrify the pious man. At
once inner and outer, these abject creatures not only assailed the person but
were also of the person. In devotional
literature through the seventeenth-century, they were calls for both a contemptus mundi and a self-contempt, being at once demonic enticements and projective
fantasies, personified sin and sinning person. Describing Bosch’s St. Anthony, Siguena refers with awe to the maker of
these monstrosities:
We see .. . the unbounded
fantasies and monstrosities that the enemy devises in order to confuse his
imperturbable soul and distract his fervent love: to this end he conjures up
living beings, wild animals, chimeras, monsters, fire, death, roaring,
threats, vipers, lions, dragons and fearful birds of all kinds, so that one
asks in astonishment how it was possible for him to give shape to all his
ideas.55
The “he” here
is ambiguous, referring first to the devil, who conjures demons to corrupt the
hermit-saint, but then to Bosch, who pictures demons to edify the viewer. This
prefigures the uncertainty in the Bosch literature about artist’s relation to
his work: whether Bosch vilifies apostasy or is himself apostate, whether his Garden is a paradise or a hell, whether he believes
or parodies belief. Bosch’s pictorial style makes such distinctions unclear.56
Refusing to model things in their distinct materiality, blurring the
boundaries between mineral, vegetable, animal, human, and spirit and all into
erratic plays of paint, Bosch puts his viewers in an uncertain—one wants to say
“contingent”—relation to everything they see.
In
1604, Carel van Mander wrote that Bosch distinguished himself by his swift,
energetic technique, executing his figures in one go.5' In contrast
to the meticulous layering of translucent glazes so admired in other
Netherlandish painters, in which the artist’s hand is wholly effaced, Bosch’s
pictures display the temporality of their making. Their wild outlines,
flickering highlights, and textured surfaces announce that they were created as
an act of will. And the many pentimenti left
visible testify that what is, in Bosch, could indeed have been otherwise.
Bosch’s spontaneous forms share features with those aleatory treasures of the Kunstkammer, in which natural objects are worked to
seem other than they are: in the background of the left inner panel, Bosch
turns a mound of earth into a man’s buttocks by a few stokes of the brush.
Devilry
is an exercise in projective imagination. In the central panel’s foreground,
Bosch harnesses a fish like a jousting horse. Spatially estranged, the armor
also reads as a ship’s rigging, which, in turn, turns the fish into a
decorative ship’s prow, and so forth. What results is the unique creation, the
radical singularity that, having no category, would be classed in the KunsU und Wunderkammer as “error,” there to be
demonized as evidence of sin, or celebrated as exemplar of fancy, or (as in
Lorraine Daston’s 1991 account) naturalized as fact, or indeed all simultaneously,
in that ambivalence toward the world’s “curiosities” that Bosch presages for
the early modem period.58
In
Bosch, a palpable sense of contingency extends beyond his individual creatures
to the spatial structure of his scenes. Again contrasting to Netherlandish
painting before him, Bosch refuses to obey the rules of linear perspective. He
builds eccentric architectures that recede chaotically toward an undeterminable
distance. Yet even as he refuses the systematic space of perspective, and even
as he strews his figures like random blots on the picture surface,59
he also creates, indeed for the first time in Western art, a coherent,
infinite worldscape. And this worldscape, in turn, is subordinated to framing
structures, to geometries and necessary placements that diagram an absolute—indeed
a non-perspectival—point of view. Bosch’s curious penchant for the roundel and
the rota, and for eccentric formats that baffle any sense of the image as
Albertian open window, work to place the world as it is experienced
contingently from within into a fixed and necessary framework opposed from
without.
The
point about Bosch’s St. Anthony is that, as Christian exemplar, Anthony is able
to see through the illusions assembled around him, to penetrate beyond the
world’s accidents to the necessary substance itself. In the central panel of
the Lisbon triptych, the saint kneels in prayer before a destroyed chapel. His
right hand, doubled by the pointing hand of Christ, directs our gaze toward the
cross on the altar. This crucifix, one presumes, both symbolizes Christ’s
presence in the Mass (again, as substance of the accidents of the bread) and
represents an ordinary corpus Christi as was
usual (and, after Trent, required) for altars. Itself most probably a working
altarpiece, Bosch’s triptych tells its viewers to look at Christ. In the ritual
context of the altar, this means beholding Christ in the elevatio. Yet by doubling the scene before the
altar, by making altar and altarpiece the subject of an altarpiece, Bosch places
Christ in a hall of mirrors. This the viewer must traverse by way of the
painting’s great temptation.
St.
Anthony’s temptation consists of a host of parodies. Traditional subjects of
religious art and drama appear as if in devilish caricatures: on the far right
of the central panel, for example, the scaly tailed tree-woman mounted backward
on a giant rat and bearing a swaddled infant, together with the poor, bearded
man wearing a blue hat behind, suggest Mary, Christ, and Joseph in their flight
into Egypt, while the surrounding three figures hint at images of the Magi.60
Sacred service appears travestied by devils: just below and to the right of
Anthony, three demons in the shape of clerics (a priest and two monks) appear
to read prayers from a breviary. And the Eucharistic sacrament is mimicked in a
Black Mass performed just behind Anthony’s back.61 An
egg born aloft by a frog stands for the elevated Host.
Even
the tiny crucifix in the chapel—that last vestige of visual truth and reference
of both Anthony’s and Christ’s deictic gestures—has its own anti-image within
the triptych. Just to the right of the crucifix and exactly aligned with it,
the ruined column displays, as though in a fresco decoration or in polychromed
low-relief, the Golden Calf in a scene of its adoration by idolatrous
Israelites. Bosch includes this mise en abyme, this painting within a painting, as if it were itself a remnant of an
idolatrous culture: just below the picture of the Adoration of the Golden Calf,
another ostensible fresco, or relief, exhibits a monkey-demon (or monkey-demon
statue) enthroned on a drum and approached by suppliants bearing gifts. And
below this is another scene, almost
certainly of two Israelites with grapes from the valley of Eschol, and
suggestive, perhaps, of a worldly abundance that diverts man from God.62
Within the triptych’s larger picture, then, the Christian chapel would seem to
occupy the ruins of an ancient pagan (or, more likely, Jewish) temple, even as
it is now threatened by a reoccupation by
modern demons and idolaters—indeed specifically by Islam, hinted at in the crescent
moon on a flag in the left inner shutter.
Bosch’s
painting of a painting of the Golden Calf, placed beside an altarpiece in
Bosch’s altarpiece, asks tough questions about the role of images in Christian
devotion. The Calf, and with it all the other temptations, enclose the saint
like a ruined, eternal envelope, or like the shattered crystal orb of the
world. And at the core of Bosch’s picture, as the geometric center of his
painted panel, the saint looks directly out at us. His eye literally places the
contingency of the world into a necessary framework.
Bosch
was a master of pictures that see us. His early panel of the Seven Deadly Sins
monumentalizes this outward gaze (Figure 6). From Siguen^a’s account, we know
that the panel once hung in the Escorial, in the bedroom of Philip II,63
the inner windows of which opened, like the fenestration of a private chapel,
to San Lorenzo’s great domed church. Bosch’s roundel takes the form of a giant
eye that warns, in the inscription around the pupil, “Beware, beware, God
sees.” At the pupil’s center, as either the image in the eye, or a reflected
image of that which the eye sees, stands Christ resurrected from his grave and
displaying his wounds. The image recalls the Holy Sepulchre at the world’s
navel, Jerusalem, in the Ebstorf mappamundi,
here translated into a veristic image that can capture Christ’s reflection as
it is cast on the shiny stone of his tomb. Moreover, by turning his painting
into an eye, Bosch reverses our usual orientation to images as active viewers
to objects passively seen. He makes his work return our glance, indeed hold us
in its gaze as we are revealed in our various sins. Read within the figure of
the eye, the seven little scenes—representing the sins of anger, vanity, lust,
lethargy, gluttony, avarice, and envy—appear as reflections on the eye’s white.
These scenes, sometimes cited as the first genre paintings of the Netherlandish
tradition, together constitute a worldscape of a kind, one wrapped around
itself, like the world’s orb turned inside out and upside down. The picture, it
is implied, visualizes sin as the world-upside-down, here as contingent images
on the periphery of God’s all- seeing eye. His is a world picture where the Weltanschauung is God’s.
In
the Lisbon St. Anthony, Bosch reduces this
all-seeing gaze to one spot of paint at the picture’s center, yet with it he
announces the continued necessity of the center. Centers, as the Golden Calf
attests, can be dangerous things, tempting the eye to an interest in the things
of the world. Bosch justifies his picture by establishing at its midpoint not
an object but a subject, not a thing or curiosity seen but a seer who views us
as a curiosity: the inner person with eyes fixed on necessary things. Anthony’s
outward glaze, which, like the giant eye in the Prado Seven Deadly Sins, interpellates and judges
us, may stand surrounded by
images of our temptations and our misdeeds. Yet painting is not only that
wondrous distraction but retains at its geometric center the truth of a holy
face.
As fate would
have it, the center did not hold. Bosch’s imitators ignored the underlying
centers, symmetries, and diagrams that locate contingency within a necessary
order. Boschian space becomes a surface strewn with clever inventions: demons,
arabesques, and saints, all delectable in their variety.64 Where
Bosch labeled the world’s contingency as a temptation around a centered inner
self, his future followers and fans took the bait and collected Bosch himself
as a “curiosity.” Their savagery forgotten, his paintings were installed in
the space of the art collection. There they would have hung like catalogues of
the very exotica that surrounded them: the jokes of nature, the images made by
chance, the ethnographic souvenirs, the moralizing prints and
pagan gemstones, and the ingenious instruments of art, knowledge, and hygiene.
From the diabolical, indecipherable, savage unknown was born the quintessential
alternative reality: the modern work of art.
In Bosch, demons
remain demons, however obscure their message might be. Only in his reception do
they become playacted savages and carnival props. Consider the savages of
Bosch’s great modernizer, Pieter Bruegel. In his one extant woodcut, dated
1566, Bruegel shows a king and a wildman on a village street (Figure 7). The
ruler, it seems, encounters ruleless natural man. Yet the longer we look, the
more artificial this difference appears. The wildman’s body seems covered by
fur, yet the regularized tufts, as well as the gap between these and the
wildman’s hands and feet, suggest a fur garment. And the wild eyes that peer
forth from a shock of hair become, on inspection, eyes of a mask. The king,
too, is a masquerade. He is a peasant whose crude artifice Bruegel marks by
shading the line between face and beard, and by balancing the crown like a pot
on top of a fur cap. Once recognized for what it is—mere rustic entertainment—everything
falls in place. The woman to the right is faceless because she too wears a
mask; and the crowd in the window locates the play in the street, before a
village tavern or brothel. Indeed the scene shows an episode from the popular
Flemish
play “Ourson
and Valentine,” in which twins, divided at birth, meet again as knight and
wildman.
Bruegel’s
woodcut exposes the peasants’ play. What we took to be natural man was merely a
local rustic in carnival clothes. And what therefore seemed like crudeness on
Bruegel’s part—the unadept treatment of fur, eyes, and crown—turns out to be
peasant artifice. This placement of “wildman” in quotes would have been
unthinkable in Bosch, who appropriated popular symbolism without ever marking
it as popular, which is to say, as other than his own. Bruegel unmasks the
wildman by exposing the seams of his outfit, suggesting that savagery is a
myth, and that Bruegel’s art itself only seems strange,
foreign, and exotic.
It
may be extravagant to discern in a printed line the burden of modernity. The
visible gap, in Bruegel’s woodcut, between face and mask, which levels wildman
and king to rustic players, and declares their art, and indeed culture itself,
to be contingent, might simply be a consequence of the graphic mark itself. It
might be argued that woodcuts were incapable of achieving, through their heavy
lines, the finish demanded for Bruegel’s legendary “realism,” hence the unique
status of this print within the artist’s oeuvre.
Yet it is precisely realism, as the figure of a rejection of artifice,65
that demands marks to place nature and natural language in quotations.
At
1572, Domenicus Lampsonius, Netherlandish painting’s first panegyrist, called
Bruegel “this new Jeroon Bos.”66 And Van Mander named Bruegel as the
greatest of the sixteenth-century Boschiads—those generally nameless epigones
who satisfied the public demand for aestheticized devilry, or disparates, during the half century between Bosch’s
death in 1516 and the Netherlands Iconoclasm of 1566. However, no artist makes
Bosch seem more historically remote, and more different from ourselves, than
does Bruegel. In Bruegel the devil becomes situated, as the specificity of an
artifice or a symbolism that can be viewed with wonder from without, while at
the same time evil—as the cruelties of war, punishment, and
indifference—derives now relentlessly from the notion “man.” The telltale lines
in the Masquerade woodcut that locate wildness
in the practices and beliefs particular to one culture, are unthinkable in
Bosch perhaps because he belonged fully to the culture that Bruegel marks as
past or primitive, because (I am tempted to say) Bosch still believed in the
monsters he painted. The world is contingent in relation to a faith that is
not. St. Anthony occupies the absolute center of the painting because the
devils around him are not advocates of competing faiths but instigators of
apostasy. What Bruegel’s markings betray is the Copernican turn, occasioned by
the European Reformation that intervened in the half century after Bosch’s
death, and by the great wars of religion that raged in his own country, that
belief itself is contingent on person, time, and place.
Van
Mander reports that Bruegel, together with one of his patrons, the merchant
Hans Franckert, “went out of town among the peasants ... to fun-fairs and
weddings, dressed in peasants’ costume, and
they gave presents just like the others, pretending to be family or
acquaintances of the bride or the bridegroom.”67 The woodcut wildman
has the quality of anthropological field notes. At the same time as the savage
becomes familiarized as peasant artifice, the peasant himself becomes unknown.
He is not nat- ural man, for he possesses art, and thus he appears to be
already embarked on the passage to Bruegel’s civility. Yet because his
artifice is transparent, unlike Bruegel’s, he becomes the native of an
alternative reality, with its artifice existing side by side with Bruegel’s.
Staring out at us not as eyes but as mask, Bruegel’s quotidian other bespeaks
the modern conditions. World pictures are contingent, not found but made. Henceforth
they will be plural.
Notes
1.
This essay began as a plenary lecture for the
conference “Alternative Realities: Medieval and Renaissance Inquires into the
Nature of the World,” held at Barnard College in December 1994. My thanks go to
Antonella Ansani and her colleagues for their kind invitation to speak. My use
of the term “contingency” derives from the workshop “Poetik und Hermeneutik,” where
I have twice been a grateful participant. Its 1994 meeting, organized by
Gerhart von Graevenitz and Odo Marquard, was specifically devoted to “Kontingenz.”
I also wish to thank Yve-Alain Bois,
Susan Buenger, Nick Cahill, Cay Cashman, ]effrey Hamburger, Serafin
Moralejo, and James Marrow for their advice and support. This essay is
dedicated to Hans Blumenberg (1920-1996).
2.
Lévi-Strauss,
Tristes
Tropiques, trans. John and Doreen Wrightman (New York,
1973), pp. 325-26.
3.
Lévi-Strauss,
p. 335.
4.
Ibid., p. 333.
5.
Ibid., p. 344.
6.
Hans
Blumenberg, “Kontingenz,” in Religion in Geschichte und Gegenwart,
3rd ed., ed. Kurt Galling (Tübingen, 1959), vol. 3, 1793-1794; Hans Poser, “Kontingenz I. Philosophisch,” Theologische
Realenzyklopädie, ed. Gerhard Müller (Berlin, 1977), pp. 544-58;
Erhard Scheibe, “Die Zunahme des Kontingenten in der Wissenschaft,” Neue Hefte für
Philosophie 24-25 ( 1985): 5.
7.
Ludwig
Feuerbach, Sämtliche
Werke, ed. Friedrich Jodl (Stuttgart, 1960), p. 310; cited in
Hans Blu- menberg, Lebenszeit und Weltzeit (Frankfurt, 1986), p. 54-
8.
Blumenberg,
Lebenszeit,
p. 55.
9.
Gemeinschaft
und Gesellschaft (Leipzig, 1887).
10.
Husserl,
“Kant und die Idee der Transzendentalphilosophie” (1924), ed. Rudolf Boehm, Husseriliana (Hague,
1924), vol. 7, p. 232; see Blumenberg, Lebenszeit, pp. 10-68.
11.
Pierre Bourdieu, Logic
of Practice, trans. RichardNice
(Stanford, 1990).
12.
Most powerfully Henri Lefebvre, The Production of Space, trans. Donald Nicholson-Smith (Oxford, 1991).
13.
Richard Rorty, Contingency,
Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge, 1989), p. 3.
14.
Blumenberg,
“Wirklichkeitsbegriff und Möglichkeit des Romans,” Nachahmung und Illusion, ed. H. R.
Jauß, Poetik und Hermeneutik, 1 (Munich, 1964), pp. 12-13.
15.
Kant, Critique of
Judgment, trans. Werner S. Pluhar (Indianapolis, 1987), p. 111.
16.
Erwin Panofsky, Perspective
as Symbolic Form, trans. Christopher Wood (New York, 1991), p. 41.
17.
On this process, see Hans Blumenberg, The Legitimacy of the Modem Age, trans. Robert M.
Wallace (Cambridge, 1983), part 3.
18.
Erwin Panofsky, Early
Netherlandish Painting (Cambridge, 1958), vol. 1, pp. 163-64-
19. The
classic formulation of this is Johan Huizinga’s 1919 The Autumn of the Middle Ages (trans. Rodney J.
Paynton and Ulrich Mammitzsch [Chicago, 1996]).
20. Daniel
Boorstin, The Discoverers (New York: Vintage
Books and Random House, 1985).
21. Camille Flammarion, L’Atmosphere: Météorologie
populaire (Paris, 1888); the attribution is Fritz
Krafft’s in “Die Stellung des Menschen im Universum,” Zur Entwicklung der
Geographie, ed. Manfred Büttner (Paderborn, 1982), pp. 147-81.
22. Martin Heidegger, “Die Zeit des
Weltbildes” (1938), Holzwege (Frankfurt, 1950), pp. 73-110.
23. Lodovico Guicciardini, Description de tous les Päis Bas (Antwerp, 1567), p. 132.
24. Felipe de Guevara, Comentarios de la
Pintura, ed. Antonio
Ponz (Madrid, 1788), p. 44; excerpted and translated in Charles de Tolnay, Hieronymus
Bosch (New York, 1965), p. 401.
25.
Wilhelm Fraenger, Hieronymus Bosch. Das tausendjährige Reich (Coburg, 1947).
26. Erwin
Panofsky, Early Netherlandish Painting, vol.
1, p. 358; quoting Adelphus Müelich, German translation of Ficino’s De vita triplica (Medicinarius
[Strasbourg, 1505], fol. 174v).
27. For
example, Dirk Bax’s aptly titled Ontcijfering
vanjeroen Bosch (The Hague, 1949).
28.
Albert Cook, Changing
the Signs: The Fifteenth-Century Breakthrough
(Lincoln, Nebr., 1985), pp. 81-120.
29. Tercera parte de la Historia de la Orden
de S. Geronimo (Madrid, 1605), p. 837; the whole passage on Bosch (in
the original, pp. 837-41) is translated in De Tolnay, Bosch, pp. 401-04.
30. Maxime Chevalair and Robert Jammes,
“Supplément aux ‘Copias de disparates’,”
Mélanges
offert à Marcel Bataillon (Bordeau, 1962), pp. 358-71.
31. See
Helmut Heidenreich,
“Hieronymus Bosch in some
Literary Contexts,” Journal of the Warburg and
Courtauld Institutes 33 (1970): 171-99.
32. X. de Salas, El Bosco en la
literatura espanola (Barcelona, 1946).
33. See references in note 6; also Franz Josef
Wetz, “Kontingenz der Welt,” Kontingenz, ed. Gerhart von Graevenitz and Odo Marquard, Poetik
und Hermeneutik, 17 (forthcoming).
34. Michel
de Certeau, The Mystic Fable, trans. Michael
B. Smith (Chicago, 1992), p. 66.
35. De
Tolnay, Bosch, app. pl. 88.
36. Ibid., cat. 1.
37. The term appears first in Eberhard
Freiherr von Bodenhausen, Gerard David und seine Schule (Munich, 1905), p. 209.
38. Lotte
Brand Philip, “The ‘Peddler’ by Hieronymus Bosch: A Study in Detection,” Nederlands Kunst- historischJaarboek
9 (1958): 1-81.
39. Hans Belting, Die Erfindung des Gemäldes (Munich,
1994), p. 123.
40. Joseph Braun, Das christliche Altar (Munich 1924),
pp. 525-56.
41. For
a recent account, with an updated bibliography, see Miri Rubin, Corpus Christi: The Eucharist in Late Medieval Culture,
p. 65, passim.
42. De Tolnay, Bosch, cat. 31.
43. See,
most recently, Ein Weltbild vor Columbus. Die Ebstorfer
Weltkarte, ed. Hartmut
Kugler (Wein- heim, 1991).
44. “Datierung und Gebrauch der Ebstorfer
Weltkarte und ihre Beziehungen zu den Nachbarklöstem Lüne und Wienhausen,” in
Kugler, Weltbild,
pp. 245-59.
45. The
relevant sources are given in Marcia Kupfer, “Medieval World Maps: Embedded
Images, Interpretive Frames,” Word and Image
10 ( 1994): 273-76. Kupfer needlessly rejects the view that the map was
originally part of the triptych.
46. This
feature has been observed by Klaus Clausberg,
“Scheibe, Rad, Zifferblatt,” in Weltbild, p. 280.
47.
Gert Unverfehrt, Hieronymus Bosch. Die Rezeption seiner Kunst im
frühen 16. Jahrhundert (Berlin, 1980), pp. 151-86.
48. De Tolnay, Bosch, p. 403.
49.
Bax, Hieronymus Bosch, p. 3.
50.
Bosch’s chief sources are translations of
Athanasius’ Greek Vitae Patrum (the Latin is
given in the Patrología Latina 73: 126ff.); on Bosch’s vernacular sources,
see Bax, Hieronymus Bosch, pp. 7-12.
51.
De Tolnay,
Bosch, cat. 24.
52.
Ibid., p. 402.
53.
On Bosch and the devotio
moderna, see Paul Vandenbroeck, Hieronymous Bosch. Tussen volksleven en stadscultuur
(Berchem, 1987), p. 120, passim.
54.
Jean Michel Massing, “Sicut erat in diebus
Antonii: The Devils Under the Bridge in the Tribulations
of St. Antony by Hieronymus Bosch in Lisbon,” in Sight and Insight: Essays on Art and Culture in Honor of
E. H. Gombrich at 85, ed. John Onians (London, 1994), pp. 108-27.
55.
De Tolnay,
Bosch, p. 402.
56.
Daniela Hammer-Tugendhat, Hieronymous Bosch. Eine historische Interpretation
seiner Gestaltung- sprinzipien (Munich, 1981), pp. 55-61.
57.
The Lives of the
Illustrious Netherlandish and German Painters, ed. and trans. Hessel Miedema (Doom- spijk, 1994),
vol. 1, p. 125.
58.
Lorraine Daston, “Marvelous Facts and Miraculous
Evidence in Early Modem Europe,” Critical Inquiry
18 (1991): 93-124- On the museological category of “error” as historically
constitutive of the idea of “art,” see Horst Bredekamp, Antikensehnsucht und Maschinenglauben (Berlin,
1993), p. 21.
59.
Compare
Hans Sedlmayr’s comments on Bruegel in “Die ‘Macchia’ Bruegels,” Jahrbuch der kunsthis-
torischen Sammlungen in Wien, n.s. 8 (1934): 137-59.
60.
Bax, Hieronymus Bosch,
p. 113; Ludwig von Baldass, Hieronymus Bosch (Vienna, 1943), p. 245.
61.
First noted in Enrico Castelli, II demoniaco nell’ arte (Milan, 1958),
on travestied Eucharists in Bosch, see Jeffrey Hamburger, “Bosch’s ‘Conjurer’:
An Attack on Magic and Sacramental Heresy,” Simiolus
14 (1984): 5-24.
62.
Bax, Hieronymus
Bosch, p. 117.
63.
Recorded by Siguença (De Tolnay, Bosch, p.
403).
64.
On Bosch imitators, see Unverfehrt, Hieronymus Bosch, pp. 122-235.
65.
On Bruegel’s realism as an anti-artifice, see
David Freedberg, The Prints of Pieter Bruegel the
Elder (Tokyo, 1989), pp. 53-65.
66.
Lampsonius,
Les
effigies des peintres célèbres des Pays-Bas, ed. Jean Puraye (Liège, 1956), pp. 60-61.
67.
Lives, vol. 1,190.
In: Picturing Science Producing Art. Edited by Caroline A. Jones and Peter Galison. London, Routledge, 1998, pp. 297-323.
Quantum Binary Signals
ResponderExcluirGet professional trading signals sent to your cell phone daily.
Follow our trades NOW & profit up to 270% daily.